Search engine for discovering works of Art, research articles, and books related to Art and Culture
ShareThis
Javascript must be enabled to continue!

Truth in Art, and Erik Satie's Judgement

View through CrossRef
AbstractIt is certainly true that Satie, in his later years, did not tire of repeating that there is ‘no Truth in Art’; and in saying so, he was doubtless very much in tune with the spirit of his artistic milieu, which included, after all, such aesthetic anarchists as Picabia and Tzara, as well as the great artistic revolutionaries of the time, Picasso and Stravinsky, for whom he had unbounded admiration. And every time he did so, he was careful to attribute the erroneous belief that there is a Truth in Art to that class of writers whom he variously called ‘critiques’, ‘pédagogues’, ‘Pontifes’, ‘pions’: people of the serious persuasion, who think it is possible to teach or describe what makes a piece of art good or bad. Attacks against this tribe are, in fact, the staple of Satie's writings. It might appear sensible to infer from this that it would be foolish for a critic to look for Truth in Erik Satie's writings about art. Nonetheless, that is what I shall be doing in this article. I shall argue that, while there may, for Satie, be no truth in art, there are truths about art, susceptible of at least indirect expression, which Satie himself maintained with remarkable adroitness. Whether those truths are peculiar to the aesthetics of Satie's writings; whether they are relevant to the way we might appreciate his music; and whether they have echoes in the thought of his artistic companions (especially those mentioned above) – these are questions that will remain open; but I would like at least to suggest that they are worth asking.
Cambridge University Press (CUP)
Title: Truth in Art, and Erik Satie's Judgement
Description:
AbstractIt is certainly true that Satie, in his later years, did not tire of repeating that there is ‘no Truth in Art’; and in saying so, he was doubtless very much in tune with the spirit of his artistic milieu, which included, after all, such aesthetic anarchists as Picabia and Tzara, as well as the great artistic revolutionaries of the time, Picasso and Stravinsky, for whom he had unbounded admiration.
And every time he did so, he was careful to attribute the erroneous belief that there is a Truth in Art to that class of writers whom he variously called ‘critiques’, ‘pédagogues’, ‘Pontifes’, ‘pions’: people of the serious persuasion, who think it is possible to teach or describe what makes a piece of art good or bad.
Attacks against this tribe are, in fact, the staple of Satie's writings.
It might appear sensible to infer from this that it would be foolish for a critic to look for Truth in Erik Satie's writings about art.
Nonetheless, that is what I shall be doing in this article.
I shall argue that, while there may, for Satie, be no truth in art, there are truths about art, susceptible of at least indirect expression, which Satie himself maintained with remarkable adroitness.
Whether those truths are peculiar to the aesthetics of Satie's writings; whether they are relevant to the way we might appreciate his music; and whether they have echoes in the thought of his artistic companions (especially those mentioned above) – these are questions that will remain open; but I would like at least to suggest that they are worth asking.

Related Results

“How could you tell how much of it was lies?” The controversy of truth in George Orwell's Nineteen Eighty-Four
“How could you tell how much of it was lies?” The controversy of truth in George Orwell's Nineteen Eighty-Four
Abstract This article considers the controversial nature of truth in George Orwell's Nineteen Eight-Four, both within the novel itself and in critical responses to i...
Landscape as Music, Landscape as Truth: Schubert and the Burden of Repetition
Landscape as Music, Landscape as Truth: Schubert and the Burden of Repetition
Adorno's essay on Schubert opens by invoking a fraught move across the threshold that separates the death of Beethoven from the death of Schubert. He goes on to read Schubert's mus...
Fictional Content
Fictional Content
Abstract It is usually taken for granted that a necessary condition for knowing that P is the truth of P. It may therefore be claimed that if we assume that we gain ...
Entrevista a Erik van der Weijde
Entrevista a Erik van der Weijde
El trabajo de Erik van der Weijde está tramado por una práctica fotográfica considerada desde múltiples perspectivas convergentes. La apropiación y producción de imágenes configura...
Gerard Manley Hopkins and Ruskin’s Idea of the Christian Artist
Gerard Manley Hopkins and Ruskin’s Idea of the Christian Artist
Abstract John Ruskin gave Gerard Manley Hopkins an aesthetic vocabulary imbued with Christian concepts of obedience, sacrifice, truth, and Divine Beauty. Even secular art is ne...
Negotiating autobiographical truth: Embodying sensation in the narrative screenplay
Negotiating autobiographical truth: Embodying sensation in the narrative screenplay
This article examines how screenwriting adaptations of written material speak of levels of truth-telling within various autobiographical texts. These include literary adaptations b...
A MINIMALIST EXPLANATION OF TRUTH’S ASYMMETRY
A MINIMALIST EXPLANATION OF TRUTH’S ASYMMETRY
Abstract Suppose that Eleanor is drowsy. Truth’s asymmetry is illustrated by the following fact: while we accept that <Eleanor is drowsy> is true becau...
Some Aspects of Rhythm and Expression in Performances of Erik Satie's "Gnossienne No. 5"
Some Aspects of Rhythm and Expression in Performances of Erik Satie's "Gnossienne No. 5"
Timing data from piano performances of Gnossienne no. 5 are analyzed to examine the way in which a performer structures different subdivisions of a constant beat. The piece contain...

Back to Top